Final update: The conversation ended with Spencer in self-referential absurdity. I post the dialogue here so that I and others can use it as an illustration in teaching. It is an example similar to a Socratic dialogue with sophists. Here, Spencer denies that we can be certain about reality while asking for answers about reality. On the pretense of evaluating an original argument about what is eternal, it is quickly evident that the main point of contention is that some basic things are clear to reason. In Socratic dialogues, the sophists try to point out contradictions in others but don’t see their own self-contradiction. This is where they are without excuse.
By way of contrast, I maintain that some things must be clear to avoid meaninglessness. If nothing is clear then this includes anything we think or say. Such thoughts aren’t clear, or, such thoughts are meaningless. We can’t ask for “clarification” because nothing is clear. Any claim to the contrary isn’t clearly different than its opposite. The immediate subject is about what is eternal and presupposes that we can distinguish “eternal” from “non-eternal.”
Spencer asks why we must begin thought with the laws of thought instead of a shared intuition or common sense (he doesn’t define these). I point out that the laws of thought, for instance the law of identity (a is a), are inescapable. When we use intuition we are using intuition and not non-intuition. For thought, the laws of thought are the highest and self-attesting authority. They cannot be questioned because they make questioning possible. In this they are different than all other authorities. Whatever else we appeal to in thought, we are making use of the laws of thought. Any argument we give relies on the laws of thought. As an experiment to see if this is the case you can try to think a thought that isn’t a thought. Try to escape reason and give an explanation about doing so (an explanation that is a non-explanation). This is the self-referential absurdity.
As in the Socratic dialogues, many red herrings are brought up to try and distract from the main subject. Socrates is accused of not answering questions when the sophist doesn’t see the thrust of his reply. The sophists ask for answers and arguments and then disregard them. Although the sophists will try to point out contradictions (thus using the law of non-contradiction) they do not see this inconsistency as it applies to their own claims about the laws of thought. In the end, the sophists say that knowledge of what is real is not possible and we only have so many competing intuitions that vie for power through persuasive talk. The sophists will say that Socrates has no answer or has begged the question not realizing their own self-contradiction has undermined such claims.
The academy that Plato started collapsed into this same sophism. I explore this in my book Faith and Reason at Early Princeton. This is where we get the name “Academic Skeptic.” It shouldn’t surprise us if today many in the academy continue that same Academic Skepticism without much self-awareness.
Discussion is only possible when the participants are committed to reason. There is no reason to continue otherwise. There is no reason to answer such a person. In fact, we have a rational obligation to avoid foolish arguments.
This example should teach us the beginning of wisdom. The light shines in the darkness but the darkness has not understood it. Let us renew the pursuit of knowing what is real so that we can choose what is good.
—
Update: I continue to update the discussion here so that there is a record of it. However, for most it is probably too long to be of interest at this point. The main argument that continues as a thread throughout is that without the laws of thought we lose the intelligibility of any claim. Even the claim that the laws of thought do not apply to reality becomes itself unintelligible–it not longer is itself or means what it means. So we cannot evaluate an argument because it might be that to evaluate really is to not evaluate. Nor can we have a discussion together since it might be that to have a discussion is to not have a discussion. The thread below ends because maybe agreeing is the same as disagreeing. This highlights the impossibility of denying the laws of thought and retaining intelligibility but also the extent to which persons will go to avoid reason.
—
I continue to update the discussion below. The initial topic is whether we can use reason to know God. One step in that is knowing that we, finite minds, are not God. We can infer what would be true of us had we existed from eternity in order to conclude that we have not existed from eternity. But most of the discussion is on whether or not we can use reason to understand what is real. One way to say this is that reason is ontological: it applies to being as well as thought. If we do not share this as common ground we will be hindered from analyzing the initial argument.
What are the necessary conditions for thought and discussion? Are there laws of thought? Is there common ground for discussion? Many of you have been asking me about my discussion with Spencer Hawkins on how to approach an argument. Below is the public dialogue I had in the comment section of this youtube video. The video itself is about unity among Christians and the role of general revelation.
In this discussion you can see the progress from the subject “what is eternal,” to his claiming that ‘a’ is ‘a’ is fallible while still thinking he needs an answer that would assume the distinction between ‘a’ and ‘non-a.’ He raises many side questions to try to divert attention from the original question but these are listed so that they can be dealt with one at a time. The original question is the standard one for philosophical skeptics: can we know anything outside of our epistemic horizon, or our experience? He initially wants to ask this about eternal being but in order to understand how epistemic horizons work we must first ask in what way they apply to us. Ultimately, the philosophical skeptic cannot even acknowledge that ‘a’ is ‘a’ is not fallible and yet attempts to affirm that there is an excuse for failing to know if anything is clear. Without ‘a’ is ‘a’ in place we cannot distinguish between self and non-self, God and non-God, eternal and non-eternal, being and non-being, and so are unable to answer why an eternal mind would have infinite knowledge. There is no “reason” to continue; in fact, we have an rational obligation to avoid foolish arguments.
—
Spencer Hawkins
1:08:35 Gangadean’s argument that the human soul is not eternal is unsound: (1) I have one thought after another. (2) If (1) and my soul were eternal, then I would be eternal in time. (3) If I were eternal in time, then I would be all knowing. (4) I am not all knowing. (5) So, I am not eternal in time. I think (3) is wrong: it’s possible for a thinking soul to exist for an eternity and never possess all knowledge. For instance, if a person didn’t care about a particular subject, they would ignore or never seek out certain facts. So they could exist for an eternity and only know a finite number true propositions. Or an eternal person could lose knowledge as they gain it — they could forget or remember incorrectly. Since knowledge entails belief, if a person loses a belief they once had, then they no longer have it as a bit of knowledge. All of this seem possible, so (3) is not certain; thus, Gangadean’s conclusion that the soul is not eternal is not “clear to reason”. It seems to me the only way (3) is true is if we assume two things: a) that the soul’s memory is infallible, and b) that the eternal person is motivated to seek out true propositions in absolutely every domain (even the most boring and irrelevant). But, of course, neither are entailed by simply “existing eternally”. Gangadean seems to be merely smuggling those assumptions in without justification.
Owen Anderson
I wonder if anything at all is entailed by “eternally existing’? For instance, is what is eternal also the highest power?
Spencer Hawkins
(1), (2), (3) and (4) pretty clearly refer to the person reading or thinking about the premises. So what is implied is not a person with an infallible memory or one who is motivated to seek all true propositions in absolutely every domain of inquiry. Also, Gangadean seems to be unjustly assuming that no facts exist beyond his epistemic horizon. If his soul were eternal in time, it could still be the case that a set of undiscoverable facts exist, given his epistemic limitations. Donald Rumsfeld famously called such facts “unknown unknowns”. Ironically, the only way Gangadean could know that no “unknown unknown” facts exist is if he was all knowing!
Owen Anderson
@Spencer Hawkins That raises a few different issues: 1. Can we know anything outside of our experience? 2. What is implied by the “I” in the premises and then my initial question: 3. Can anything be entailed from “eternal.” Can we know that “a” is “a” beyond our experience?
Spencer Hawkins
@Owen Anderson the question isn’t so much whether we can know “anything” outside of our experience, it’s whether we would, if we had no temporal beginning or end, know everything. Given our human epistemic limitations, flawed memory, and erratic motivation to seek absolutely every domain of fact, it seems to me (3) is false. It seems that human persons is implied by the “I” in the premises. (4) — “I am not all knowing” — is about the reader of the argument. Gangadean (or anyone who agrees with the argument) has the burden to show why (3) is true. Are you suggesting that from the concept of “eternal being” we can logically deduce “all knowing”? Can you prove it?
Owen Anderson
@Spencer Hawkins We could add those as more issues, like:
4. Does memory lapse affect my ability to know if I am eternal?
5. Do I need to know everything before I can know anything?
Spencer Hawkins
@Owen Anderson you’re brining up questions that shift away from (3). We’re not asking whether memory lapse affects one’s ability to know if they are eternal, we’re asking a broader question, whether memory lapse affects one’s ability to know everything.
Owen Anderson
@Spencer Hawkins Far from shifting away, I’m listing your questions so we can make sure we address each of them. Yes premise 3 is true and the argument is sound. We are working through questions you have about that starting with #1 above in the list. You aren’t sure if you can know anything outside of your epistemic horizons. So I’ve asked you if you can know that “a” is “a” outside of your experience? I’ve noted your broader question, but we can’t assess the soundness of the argument together if you don’t know that “a” is “a” outside of your experience.
Spencer Hawkins
@Owen Anderson You’ve merely asserted that (3) is true and the argument is sound. All you’ve done is respond with questions back at me, instead of actually defending the truth of (3). In fact, it seems you’ve shifted to a different argument, summarized as something like the following:
Owen Anderson
@Spencer Hawkins I’m neither shifting away from your questions nor begging the question. I’m taking the time to list your questions and I’m affirming that I do think the argument is sound to clarify my own position.
Spencer Hawkins
@Owen Anderson I don’t see why you don’t just get straight to the point. If you had a proof for (3), why wouldn’t you just offer it? Same with (i) and (ii)? Or are you under the impression that philosophical proofs only come by way of Socratic dialogue? That is, are you of the belief that formal proofs aren’t meant to be shown by an individual with her pen and paper (or computer and keyboard), but through a back and forth discussion, where you help draw out the deductive implications of an interlocutor’s questions? Or moreover, do you think your interlocutor must “affirm” each and every step of the proof for you to reach your professed conclusion? If so, I simply disagree. If you have a deductive proof, you don’t need me or anyone else in the room for you to meet your burden of proof.
For instance, you could simply define your terms, state how you will evaluate the argument, state your premises, and prove them.
To answer your question, I do, in a sense, “affirm” or “know” that ‘a is a’ beyond my own experience, but not in the way that you’re assuming. I don’t claim to be deductively certain when I claim to “affirm” or “know” the meaning of terms, the consistency that the world takes, and so on. I think human knowledge is fallible and the quest for a foundationalist (internalist) basis in incorrigible or infallible certainty is a lost cause. But let’s not lose sight of Gangadean’s proof that you think is sound: the question with (3) isn’t if we can know (given your definition of knowledge) some things beyond our experience, but whether, if you or I were eternal in time, would we know everything there is to know? You affirm (3). Why?
Owen Anderson
@Spencer Hawkins I don’t think we need to engage in dialogue in all cases, and there are times when we can simply state an argument. Nor have I missed your point about whether epistemic horizons apply to an eternal being. To address that question we need to first back up and figure out what are epistemic horizons and this includes finding out how they affect us. You were concerned in your first post about whether assumptions had been smuggled in, so we need to see if you are doing the same. Your assumptions have kept you from being able to assess what is going on in the argument and then in our discussion.
These specific questions (can an eternal mind forget, be subject to decay) are ones I also had and ones my students regularly ask me. I have no problem answering them. But if one of the persons involved isn’t sure that ‘a’ is ‘a,’ then they won’t be able to go to that next step. They wouldn’t be able to affirm if a word is a word, what they are thinking is what they are thinking, their question is a question, a mind is a mind, eternal is eternal, a reply is a reply, or an argument is an argument.
Additionally, you quoted from someone who regularly slanders me and others I know. This affects whether the question is one in good faith to pursue and answer together.
On your end, I can imagine it would be difficult to understand why someone would think that an eternal being would have infinite knowledge given your fallibilism and empiricism. Its like saying: “I can’t believe in God because all is fallible, perhaps God is not God, eternal is not eternal, true is not true.” That would be a very confusing condition. If you make progress in understanding why ‘a’ is ‘a’ get back in touch with me so that we can discuss why an eternal mind would have infinite knowledge. Until then there is no “reason” to continue the discussion.
—
I know that many others are reading this and have been in contact with me on email with questions. Thank you! This has been a useful discussion to highlight when questioning becomes incoherent. It has drawn lots of attention to the video and I’m thankful for that. I can use this dialogue as a resource for others to help to illustrate what happens to a discussion when someone demands an answer but cannot even affirm that an answer is an answer due to their prior commitment to fallibilism. There are different levels of fallibilism with different applications and this seems to be one that affirms “all is fallible.” I’ll post it at my blog here: renewalphilosophy.com
In terms of epistemological assumptions, this has been similar to how Pontius Pilate questioned Jesus in John 18. When he asks Jesus “what is truth?” the discussion ends. What kind of answer does he want? A true answer? He doesn’t know what that is and wouldn’t recognize it. You can imagine Pontius Pilate thinking “I really stumped Jesus, he couldn’t reply,” while also not even knowing what truth is!
Many have told me they are surprised to see that a skeptic will go so far as to think ‘a’ is ‘a’ is fallible. We can watch and see if a skeptic can also have integrity with that profession. What would it look like to be consistent with saying each word in my sentence or question does not mean what it means? If you would like to discuss this with me, or why an eternal mind would have infinite knowledge and not be subject to memory loss or decay, follow my blog as I will update it.
Spencer Hawkins
@Owen Anderson I’m happy to hear that you acknowledge your burden of proof given your claims, however we are still without a proof for the original argument. If objections about a temporal eternal soul having a memory lapse and incomplete knowledge are common from your students, and if you don’t have a problem answering, why not just give an answer? Instead, you seem to be trying to shift a burden onto me to avoid shouldering your own — you’re shifting the focus to assumptions that I may (or may not) be making, and claiming that those assumptions prevent me from being able to assess the argument and our discussion. That is, you’re asserting that your infallibalist, internalist, foundationalist view is a coherent epistemological view (and perhaps the only coherent epistemological view), and you’re demanding that I “affirm” whole parts of your philosophy, including your view of the level of epistemic justification that we have for the laws of thought and the consistency that the world takes at every level of reality, before you’re willing to shoulder your burden of proof. This seems not only fallacious but an attempt to rhetorically hijack the conversation to keep it under your complete philosophical control.
But it doesn’t have to be like that. For one thing, I’m able to entertain philosophical ideas. I can “stand in your shoes” and attempt to evaluate the argument from your philosophical perspective, presuppositions and all. I’m not dogmatically committed to my view such that I’m unable to evaluate another philosopher’s arguments. And even if I was a hopelessly lost intellectual, you could still simply demonstrate the logical impossibility of the opposite of (3) and (1). My feeling is that you don’t have a very good proof, so you’re stalling, or you’re going to have to shift to a different argument (and abandon Gangadean’s) in order to make sense of your claim, and you don’t want to do that publicly. But I’m all ears, prove me wrong.
Next, I’d hoped that you’d be more charitable to my view. First, I’m not a card-carrying empiricist. As I already said, I do, in a sense, “affirm” and “know” that ‘a is a’ beyond my own experience. E.g. I affirm that the sun remains the sun even after it has set. I just think self-evident truths like the law of identity are grounded (or justified) through something like intuition or common sense, which is something you’ve said is “insufficient” (CGE, p. xv). Or perhaps Kant was right that ‘a is a’ is a necessary precondition of intelligibility, so I have a sort of transcendental justification for the law of identity. How far that reaches into the depths of reality, I’m not logically certain (i.e. I can’t logically rule out how things exist at the quantum level, or if, say, the law of excluded middle is universally true, or if other systems of cognition beyond our kin don’t make use of the LEM. If you can, I’m all ears).
Second, you’ve made a mess of fallibilism. I think fallible is a predicate of people, not (always) propositions. So I’m prone to mistakes in judgement, I can believe false things, and I can think I have a justification when I don’t. But my acknowledgment that I could be wrong doesn’t imply or entail that I am wrong. You seem to be making this slide: if one “affirms” fallibalism in any way, then one can’t reliably recognize the difference between “word and non-word” or “argument and non-argument.” But that doesn’t follow. For one thing, there are many kinds of falliblism. You haven’t shown that I’m incapable of having a coherent conversation by being a fallibalist. In fact, your responses to my comments demonstrate that I am capable of carrying on a conversation! Also, fallibalism doesn’t entail complete skepticism (at least you haven’t shown anything like a good argument to that end). I think it’s a kind of black and white thinking on your part to assume that epistemology is either infallibalism of the internalist, foundationalist sort, or total skepticism. It’s unfortunate that this assumption is built into Gangadean’s entire philosophy.
You said, “you quoted from someone who regularly slanders me and others I know. This affects whether the question is one in good faith to pursue and answer together.” I only know the author of reasontodoubt dot blogspot as ‘J’, and nothing more. All I do is read his articles (which I’ve found to be very helpful), and I’m not aware of any slander against you or anyone else. All I’ve seen are pointed philosophical criticisms against Rational Presuppositionalism. I will point out, however, that my citing a source that you may not personally like doesn’t affect whether what he says is true or whether his criticisms of RP are accurate. I’m still interested in hearing your proof for (3) and (1), or (i) and (ii). Or ‘J’ suggests that you prove the following claim: “‘X is eternal’ entails ‘X is the highest power.'” All this go-around, and still no proof. As you said, we don’t need to engage in dialogue and there are times when we can simply state an argument.
@Owen Anderson you said, “skeptic will go so far as to think ‘a’ is ‘a’ is fallible. We can watch and see if a skeptic can also have integrity with that profession. What would it look like to be consistent with saying *each word in my sentence or question does not mean what it means*?” I’m not saying that, and I don’t believe that. Being a fallibilist about the justification for the universal (ontological) application of the laws of thought does not imply that I think each word in your question doesn’t mean what it means. You’re confusing belief that p with belief that ~p. That is, I believe ‘a is a’ is universal. But, I acknowledge that my justification or knowledge that ‘a is a’ given all levels of reality is outstripped by my ability to prove it given your standard of proof (i.e. epistemic, absolute certainty). And in saying so, you’re accusing me of believing that ‘a is ~a’, when I don’t believe that for a second. In other words, your standard of proof is too high. You’re feigning epistemic certainty for the laws of thought given all levels of reality when you haven’t shown it. And, while I make this pretty straight forward point, you’re accusing me of believing ‘a is ~a’ (and you’re filibustering to stall the convo based on this mistake). This seems to be the kind of sophistry that philosophers try to avoid.
Owen Anderson
@Spencer Hawkins I don’t agree with most of the claims you make in your post about what I supposedly think. You’d like people to be charitable about your views so do the same. I don’t think that doubting p means you believe not p. Or that only deductive proof is permissible. Or that people only use the word “knowledge” to mean certainty. Or that I’m affirming an “infallibilist internalist foundationalist” view here. Or that I’m requiring “high epistemic standards” here. Or that we must prove the laws of thought. Or that we can only dialogue if you agree with me about everything.
Much of these misrepresentations most likely trace to your original source that you quoted. Whether or not your source sometimes says something true isn’t the problem. It is his regular use of insults and misrepresentations that is the problem. You say philosophers want to avoid sophistry and that is right. They also want to avoid those types of behavior. You’ve linked yourself to him from the very beginning of this thread and so that does affect if your question is in good faith.
I’ve been focusing on your first concern in every one of my replies since then. What are our epistemic limits? How do we understand our own fallibility and limitations? This is far from stalling or failing to have a good proof. Nevertheless, making those kinds of assertions is precisely what is slowing this down and undermining your claim to just want to deal with the question. I don’t want to shift to other concerns if we haven’t addressed this first one. What I am asking is if we have the necessary conditions for thought and discourse in place to continue on together and assess this argument. If not, it wouldn’t make sense to go on and talk about other subjects.
Where we are at now in addressing that question of epistemic horizons is this: You seem to agree that reason is transcendental, but that you do not know if it is ontological (applies to being as well as thought), is that right? You say there is still no proof. I’m asking if the necessary conditions for proof are shared given your views on your epistemic horizons. See my above comments about your example of the married bachelors:
“Like clarifying “bachelor,” once we do this with “eternal” the contradiction is there, but it was there the whole time. If someone says “I don’t see how a married bachelor is a contradiction, the burden is on you, all your work is ahead of you,” or they say “I don’t see why eternal means not temporal, the burden is on you, all your work is ahead of you,” they haven’t understood the words being used.”
Spencer Hawkins
@Owen Anderson As I said, you’re shifting a burden onto me. I don’t need to affirm anything for you to meet your burden of proof. You can simply state your justification for (3) and (1). Or, if you want, you can include what you think are the necessary conditions for thought and conversation, why they are necessary, and show how you’re not violating them. Instead, you’re trying to wrangle me into either affirming your view of the necessity of the ontology of the laws of thought, or shut me out of the conversation as a person who “denies reason”. It feels like a cheap apologetic ploy, tbh. Remember, all I’m asking is that you justify your claim that (3) is true and that Gangadean’s argument at 1:08:35 is sound (as you claimed). If you want to debate metaphysics and epistemology, let’s meet up for coffee.
You say that you don’t want to shift to other concerns if we haven’t addressed the first one, but what you’re calling the “first concern” (the question of epistemic horizons) was my third concern. My first and second concerns to (3) were, first, if a soul like yours or mine were eternal in time, the possibility remains that we wouldn’t gain all knowledge because we lack the motivation or interest to learn about every possible domain of fact, and second, we have faulty memory. Both of these possibilities seem to undermine the third premise of Gangadean’s argument.
Owen Anderson
@Spencer Hawkins I appreciate your last post, thank you. In my own case I’m ok with some formulations of externalism. And some forms of fallibilism seem to be restatements of the doctrine of total depravity and thus potentially have Calvinist origins! One of the things my first book was about is precisely this point of how the fall affects us in our pursuit of knowledge.
Spencer Hawkins
Owen Anderson
All of us in philosophy must have a thick skin about others thinking our views are false, or being told that if something we hold is true it implies something else that is false. And in religion we all need a thick skin in knowing some others think our beliefs are incorrect and could therefore lead to negative outcomes. You saying Christianity is false, or someone else saying Secular Humanism is false, is not at all the same as using insults. The best objection is to hold each other to being consistent and having integrity because this means we are affirming reason in the law of non-contradiction.
By way of contrast, we needn’t be involved in using insults or dishonesty. “Sloppy” and “lazy” are unnecessary insults. “Cult” is used because he is being dishonest about events behind anonymity. “Cult” has a specific meaning and does not apply to historic Christianity. So it doesn’t follow that if he is right about our views being false then we are a cult. That would just mean that historic Christianity (as summarized in the Westminster Confession of Faith) is false. It is an insulting term being used dishonestly and shuts down conversation. Much of what needs to be addressed is private and cannot be replied to on a public blog To say we won’t engage with him because we don’t have an answer, as opposed to because of his own behavior, is a perfect example of the dishonesty.
I hope you can see why your involving yourself with a source exhibiting such behavior is much more problematic than simply saying you think we are incorrect. You can come up with objections yourself without citing that kind of source. I’m not interested in having a proxy discussion with him through you. His private conduct toward me and others, and continued use of insults, is the reason I don’t interact with him in public spaces.
If you want to address the question of “what is eternal?” in good faith can we agree not to engage in that kind of behavior?
Spencer Hawkins
I can agree to not use terms like “lazy” and “sloppy” when addressing philosophical arguments. As I said, I am not here to insult you, but to discuss arguments, and I distance myself from any unnecessary insults. However, I don’t wish to shift to a different question in this thread before we’ve addressed your justification for (3). I’m hoping you will say something about why you think (3) is true, or offer an alternative argument to Gangadean’s (at 1:08:35). If that involves you stating your beliefs about what you think is eternal, and perhaps what you think is entailed by it, by all means, say so! But as you said, we don’t need to engage in dialogue and there are times when we can simply state an argument.
Owen Anderson
I notice that you leave out the most egregious of his regular insults, “cult,” and I’d need you to agree on not engaging with that one as well. I’m happy to discuss objections to historic Christianity and often do in my line of work. But there’s no need for such behavior. I’ll continue my reply below but will need you to address that one in your next reply before I continue this conversation.
Yes there are times when an argument can be stated without discussion but this doesn’t seem to be one of them. It is often the case that we need to back up and look at the interpretive assumptions a person is bringing to an argument. I’m currently at a professional philosophy conference and this is what most of the presenters do in their talks so it is standard procedure.
A couple of things, I think you’ve left out something important that he said in his reply to that question and so I don’t think you’ve captured his argument.
We still aren’t in agreement if we can even assess arguments. If reason isn’t ontological, reason doesn’t apply to being, then it won’t matter whether there is or is not a contradiction because perhaps there are contradictions in reality. I think reason is ontological. As I understand it you aren’t sure one way or the other. So you aren’t saying it isn’t, but you also aren’t saying it is. Perhaps the eternal is non-eternal and you’ve reached your epistemic horizons.
Spencer Hawkins
Two comments back I did mention his use of “cult”. But I will clarify: if you take it as an insult, I will refrain from using it. I haven’t used the term here. As I said, I wish to distance myself from any unnecessary insults. I’m not here to hurl insults, but to talk philosophy, particularly Gangadean’s argument at 1:08:35, which he argues, “If I were eternal in time, then I would be all knowing.” You’ve asserted the premise is true and his argument sound, but thus far we haven’t see a justification from you. Do you have good reasons to justify (3)?
I’m hoping that we don’t lose sight of the burden of proof that you have. And I’m not sure why you think that we must engage in Socratic dialogue for you to give your reasons for affirming Gangadean’s argument. Why isn’t this a case of you just stating an argument? Gangadean did just that in answering the gentleman in the audience.
Owen Anderson
Thanks for your clarification! Yes I do think Dr. Gangadean is right about the problem of being in time from eternity. But I think the formulation you’ve relied upon left out an important word he used. Maybe go back and formulate your own analysis of his argument instead of relying on another who has dishonest intentions.
He was able to give a direct answer because of common ground with the audience. And it is because of this shared common ground that the questioner quickly understood the argument and the conclusion.
In our case, we don’t have that. We don’t even agree that “a is a” applies to reality! Its not my burden to prove to you that “a is a.” And without that no other proof that you request is possible. It is a type of loaded question.
Spencer Hawkins
Which word did I leave out? Here is Gangadean’s statement of the argument at 1:08:35: “The soul is in time — we have one thought after another. If the soul were eternal, it would be eternal in time. If we were eternal in time, we’d have an infinite amount of time. If we had an infinite amount of time, we’d have… [all knowledge]. Do you have all knowledge? [No.] Then you’re not eternal.”
Formally (and charitably) stated, the argument would read:
(1) The soul is in time — we have one thought after another.
(2) If (1) and our souls were eternal, then our souls would be eternal in time.
(3) If our souls were eternal in time, then we would have all knowledge. (4) We don’t have all knowledge.
(5) Therefore, our souls are not not eternal in time.
Which word did I leave out, and how does it affect the argument? Why do you think (3) is true? We still haven’t seen a justification from you on this thread.
I do “agree” that ‘a is a’ applies to reality, in that I believe it does. However, I think we need to make two distinctions. First, between (A) the laws of thought as necessary conceptual truths, and (B) the laws of thought as both necessary conceptual truths and necessary ontological truths. I’m maximally confident (A) is true, and I’m not asking you to prove it or that you have a burden to prove it. What I’d like you to explain is the extent of justification you think you have for (B). Do you think the conjunction of (B) is clear to reason? Can you show that the other possibilities are logically impossible? I don’t see how you could ever do that. Perhaps the laws of thought are necessary conceptual truths, but are not universal or necessary ontological truths in some domains (e.g. quantum mechanics); thus (B) is not clear to reason. Or, do you think the conjunction of (B) is self-attesting or self-evident? Why think such a thing?
And second, we need to distinguish between a presupposition of experience and that which can be shown to be clear to reason about mind-independent reality beyond our experience. I think “the laws of thought apply to being” is a presupposition of experience, not something for which the contradictory can be shown to be logically impossible of the reality beyond our experience. The latter is your claim, and your burden to shoulder.
Owen Anderson
This is another good example of why we aren’t able to assess the argument. We can’t assess the argument because we don’t agree on whether the laws of thought are also laws of being (ontological). You don’t know if “eternal” is “non-eternal” in reality. And now you’ve repeated your claim that you can’t know if the laws of thought apply outside of your experience (“reality beyond our experience,” or your “epistemic horizons”). What is “eternal” is outside of your experience. Therefore, you won’t be able to know about what is eternal due to this epistemic horizon. You won’t be able to assess arguments about what is eternal. This isn’t a matter of who shoulders the burden of proof. It is a matter of whether there is sufficient common ground to have mutual understanding to proceed. As I noted above, it is a loaded question to maintain these limitations and yet ask for an argument.
Spencer Hawkins
But we do agree that the laws of thought are ontological. I’ve said in this thread that I “believe” and “agree” that ‘a is a’ applies to reality and is universal. So you’re just wrong to say that “we don’t agree on whether the laws of thought are also laws of being (ontological).” Our difference seems to be on the epistemic status of our belief that reason is ontological. I think it’s a presupposition of experience, or perhaps a non-inferential intuition. You think it’s “clear to reason”, meaning, you can show, without relying on intuition or a mere brute starting point, that reason is ontological. I’m asking what that demonstration looks like. Do you have an argument? If you insist that the only coherent “common ground” is one where we can demonstrate that reason is ontological, it would seem that you shoulder the burden to show why that’s necessary. You haven’t done that. Thus, it’s a loaded assumption on your part to maintain that we “know” (it’s “clear to reason”) or that we must “know” that reason is ontological, without showing it first. To be clear, my asking you to show how it is that you know reason is ontological without appealing to intuition or common sense is not the same as me denying that reason is ontological.
Owen Anderson
No I don’t think I’m wrong that we disagree. Here’s what you said above: “To answer your question, I do, in a sense, “affirm” or “know” that ‘a is a’ beyond my own experience, but not in the way that you’re assuming. I don’t claim to be deductively certain when I claim to “affirm” or “know” the meaning of terms, the consistency that the world takes, and so on. I think human knowledge is fallible and the quest for a foundationalist (internalist) basis in incorrigible or infallible certainty is a lost cause.” We can’t know whether “eternal” is “non-eternal” so we can’t assess the argument together.
Spencer Hawkins
Since we both believe that ‘a is a’ applies to reality, the questions now seem to be, why think that we must have clarity of basic distinctions to have intelligible discussion in the first place? This is your assumption, but it’s not obvious that you’re right. Perhaps our basic distinctions are ultimately grounded in our shared intuition, and nothing (epistemically) more. If we lack clarity at the basic level, why do you insist that discussion is impossible? Do you have an argument? (Note: I’m open to there being clarity at the basic level, if you can show it.)
In addition, why do you insist that we must have clarity of basic distinctions to have knowledge? Perhaps the epistemic justification of our most basic distinctions boils down to psychological habit, intuition or common sense. If that were the case, why is knowledge impossible? This is your assumption, but again, it’s not obvious that you’re right. Perhaps your theory of knowledge is wrong. Do you have an argument in support of your theory of knowledge?
Earlier you accused me of asking a “loaded question”, but here it seems you have your own set of philosophical principles that need to be justified.
Owen Anderson
You said “why think that we must have clarity of basic distinctions to have intelligible discussion in the first place?” Perhaps basic distinctions aren’t clear, including the distinction between agreeing and disagreeing, and really these are just the same thing. If so there isn’t much left to discuss.
Spencer Hawkins
You’re begging the question by re-asserting the very thing I’m asking you to explain. We’re trying to critically examine our most basic assumptions, right? You’re making the assumption that if we lack clarity, we lack the ability to make any and all distinctions. But maybe this assumption isn’t correct. Maybe you’re wrong. Maybe we can (and do) make distinctions sufficient for thought and speech, without clarity. Why do you assume the dichotomy of clarity or meaninglessness? Perhaps the ultimate epistemic justification for our most basic distinctions is grounded in shared intuition or common sense, or something epistemically similar, yet we’re still able to have coherent thought and speech. Please explain why all non-clarity epistemologies are impossible.
Owen Anderson
And here I thought you were the one begging the question! Your post helps illustrate why you had a hard time correctly stating the original argument and making any progress since then. Your last few replies have been ignoring my responses and now you’ve officially ended the conversation in self-referential absurdity.
Earlier I was listing the many sidetracks you were bringing up. We can add:
- I can’t understand, why won’t you give a non-circular proof that we need proof?
- I can’t understand, why isn’t there an infinite regress of proofs?
- I can’t understand, why do we begin thinking with the laws of thought?
- I can’t understand, why must we begin affirming some things are clear to avoid nihilism (the claim that nothing is clear)?
- Why can’t our ultimate source of authority in thought set aside the laws of thought?
- It isn’t clear to me what it means for something to be clear.
I’ve already given sufficient answers above to address these. Go back and try to work it out. Do we even agree on the meaning of the terms we are using? What does it mean for something to be “clear”? What does it mean for something to be “eternal”? Can we distinguish “eternal” from “non-eternal”? How? How can this be known outside of experience and epistemic horizons?
Your replies show that you haven’t given any thought to my answers. This disregard is inconsistent with asking for answers and arguments, and you have lost this one chance to work through it with me. See my last reply about why you can’t continue the discussion if nothing is clear. Try to figure out the argument and how it addresses your concerns. Figure out why your not being able to be sure about the law of identity affects each of your replies and ends the conversation.
After all, perhaps discussions aren’t really discussions!